Epidemiology Research Paper

Academic Writing Service

View sample epidemiology research paper. Browse research paper examples for more inspiration. If you need a health research paper written according to all the academic standards, you can always turn to our experienced writers for help. This is how your paper can get an A! Feel free to contact our writing service for professional assistance. We offer high-quality assignments for reasonable rates.

Abstract

The published literature on ethics in epidemiological research and public health practice has grown rapidly over the past three decades. The literature on this topic includes ethical guidelines for epidemiologists and conceptual frameworks of ethics and epidemiology. Several important topics in public health ethics have also been highlighted. Attention to ethical issues can facilitate the effective planning and conduct of epidemiological studies and the evaluation of public health programs. Addressing ethical concerns in epidemiology and public health practice is consistent with the prevention orientation of public health. Ethical concerns can be identified early and effectively addressed through careful analysis.

Academic Writing, Editing, Proofreading, And Problem Solving Services

Get 10% OFF with 24START discount code


Introduction

A rich and growing body of literature has emerged on ethics in epidemiological research and public health practice (American College of Epidemiology 2000; Beauchamp et al. 1991; Beauchamp 1996; CIOMS 1991; Coughlin et al. 1997; Coughlin 1997). The published literature includes conceptual frameworks of public health ethics and overviews of historical developments in the field (Childress et al. 2002; Coughlin et al. 1997). Several important topics in public health ethics have also been analyzed and discussed. This research paper provides an overview of ethical issues in epidemiological research and public health practice. In the discussion that follows, a summary is provided of current definitions and conceptualizations of ethics and epidemiology, public health ethics, and key ethical concerns in the field.

Background And Conceptual Clarification

As noted by Childress et al. (2002), “Public health is primarily concerned with the health of the entire population, rather than the health of individuals. Its features include an emphasis on the promotion of health and the prevention of disease and disability; the collection and use of epidemiological data, population surveillance, and other forms of empirical quantitative assessment; a recognition of the multidimensional nature of the determinants of health; and a focus on the complex interactions of many factors – biological, behavioral, social, and environmental – in developing effective interventions.” Public health activities also include community collaborations and partnerships for health and the identification of priorities for public health action.




Previous authors have identified ethical issues and core values in public health and highlighted differences and similarities between public health ethics and other areas of bioethics (Childress et al. 2002). Public health ethics, which can be defined as the identification, analysis, and resolution of ethical problems arising in public health practice and research, has different domains from those of medical ethics. Ethical concerns in public health often relate to the dual obligations of public health professionals to acquire and apply scientific knowledge aimed at restoring and protecting the public’s health while respecting individual autonomy. Ethics in public health involves interplay between protecting the welfare of the individual, as in medicine, and the public health goal of protecting the public welfare. Other ethical concerns in public health relate to the need to ensure a just distribution of public health resources. Public health ethics has a broad scope that includes ethical and social issues arising in health promotion and disease prevention, epidemiological research, and public health practice.

In conceptualizing public health ethics and distinguishing it from other areas of bioethics, previous authors have often highlighted mandatory or coercive public health measures that are authorized by public health law (e.g., quarantining people with contagious diseases such as Ebola hemorrhagic fever) or activities that may infringe upon personal privacy or autonomy, such as public health surveillance. In many public health activities, there is a tension between concerns over personal liberties and individual autonomy and public health perspectives, which may be utilitarian, paternalistic, or communitarian.

Communitarian perspectives may favor limiting individual autonomy for the sake of the common good or public interest.

Despite the importance of mandatory public health activities required by law, many examples of voluntary public health activities can be cited. Public health surveys, for instance, depend upon the support and informed consent of members of the public. In deliberating about ethical questions in their own public health activities, public health professionals have increasingly referred to explications of moral reasoning methods useful for public health research and practice.

Moral Reasoning In Public Health

Moral reasoning involves deliberating about ethical questions and reaching a decision with the help of judgment and rational analysis. In such deliberations, particular decisions and actions may be justified by ethical theory or an integrated body of rules and principles. Two theories have commonly been cited in public health research and practice: deontological and utilitarian (Beauchamp 1996). Deontological theories (sometimes referred to as Kantian theories) hold that people should not be treated as means to an end and that some actions are right or wrong regardless of the consequences. Deontological theories provide strong support for protecting research participants and whole communities of people, even if protections for human subjects slow research or the acquisition of knowledge.

Utilitarian theories, on the other hand, strive to maximize beneficial consequences. The principle of utility requires aggregate or collective benefits to be maximized. From a utilitarian perspective, the principle of utility is the ultimate ethical principle, from which all other principles are derived. Utilitarian theories provide strong justification for public health programs such as mandatory vaccination programs for children and the fluoridation of public water supplies.

Different methods of moral reasoning have been applied to ethical decision making in public health research and practice. Two approaches have figured most prominently: the principle-based approach to moral reasoning, explicated by Beauchamp and Childress, and case-based methods such as casuistry (Coughlin et al. 1997).

Principle-Based Approaches

Principle-based approaches to moral reasoning were developed to address ethical issues in clinical medicine and are not necessarily the optimal approach for analyzing ethical issues in public health. The four principles of beneficence, nonmaleficence, justice, and respect for autonomy are mentioned in ethical guidelines drafted for public health professionals, although the guidelines do not provide an exhaustive account of how the principles can be used as a framework for ethical decision making (Beauchamp 1996). Principles such as justice also figure prominently in still-evolving ethical frameworks that have been proposed for public health.

The principles of beneficence, nonmaleficence, autonomy, and justice as explained by Beauchamp and Childress seek to reduce morality to its basic elements and to provide a useful framework for ethical analysis in the health professions. The principles do not provide a full philosophical justification for decision making, however. In situations where there is conflict between principles, it may be necessary to choose between them or to assign greater weight to one. Practical problems in public health ethics require that these principles be made more applicable through a process of specification and reform. Ongoing progressive specification is needed as new issues and concerns arise.

The ethical principle of beneficence requires that potential benefits to individuals and to society be maximized and that potential harms be minimized. Beneficence involves both the protection of individual welfare and the promotion of the common welfare. This principle underlies ethical rules and norms that require that public health institutions act in a timely manner on the information they have and that they expeditiously make the information available to the public. The principle of nonmaleficence requires that harmful acts be avoided. However, the principle of nonmaleficence does not preclude balancing potential harms against potential benefits (Beauchamp 1996). The principle of autonomy focuses on the right of self-determination. Respect for the individual is a principle rooted in the Western tradition, which grants importance to individual freedom in political life and to personal development.

Principles of justice are also important. Utilitarian theories of justice emphasize a mixture of criteria so that public utility is maximized. From this perspective, a just distribution of benefits from public health programs or research is determined by the utility to all affected. As noted by Childress et al. (2002), public health activities are generally understood to be consequentialist in that the primary end that is sought is the health of the public. An egalitarian theory of justice holds that each person should share equally in the distribution of the potential benefits of health care resources such as screening services. Other theories of justice hold that society has an obligation to correct inequalities in the distribution of resources and that those who are least well off should benefit most from resources such as screening services. Such theories of justice provide considerable support for maximizing benefits to medically underserved people.

Moral disagreements can sometimes be resolved by obtaining further facts about matters at the center of the controversy or by more clearly defining the language used by disputing parties (Beauchamp 1996). Other steps that can be taken to resolve moral controversies include using examples and counterexamples and analyzing arguments to expose their inadequacies, gaps, and fallacies. In addition, moral problems can sometimes be resolved by getting the disputing parties to adopt a new policy or code, such as ethical guidelines for epidemiologists.

Ethical Dimension

The results of epidemiological research studies contribute to generalizable knowledge by elucidating the causes of disease; by combining epidemiological data with information from other disciplines such as genetics and microbiology; by evaluating the consistency of epidemiological data with etiological hypotheses; and by providing the basis for developing and evaluating health promotion and prevention procedures. The primary professional roles of epidemiology are the design and conduct of scientific research and the public health application of scientific knowledge. This includes reporting research results and maintaining and promoting health in communities. In carrying out these professional roles, epidemiologists often encounter a number of ethical issues and concerns that require careful consideration. Many of these issues have been addressed in the literature on ethics in epidemiology and public health practice including ethical guidelines.

Ethical Guidelines For Epidemiologists

Ethical and professional norms in epidemiology have been clarified in ethical guidelines for epidemiologists and other public health professionals (American College of Epidemiology 2000; Beauchamp et al. 1991; Soskolne and Light 1996; CIOMS 1991). Ethical guidelines such as those developed for the Industrial Epidemiology Forum, the International Society for Environmental Epidemiology, and the American College of Epidemiology provide useful accounts of epidemiologists’ obligations to research participants, society, employers, and colleagues. Ethical guidelines for environmental epidemiologists drafted by Colin Soskolne and Andrew Light (1996), which were adopted by the International Society for Environmental Epidemiology in 1999, highlight the important obligations that epidemiologists have to communities that are affected by environmental hazards. The ethical guidelines adopted by the American College of Epidemiology (2000) discuss core values, duties, and virtues in epidemiology; the professional role of epidemiologists; minimizing risks and protecting the welfare of research participants; providing benefits; ensuring an equitable distribution of risks and benefits; protecting confidentiality and privacy; obtaining informed consent; submitting proposed studies for ethical review; maintaining public trust; avoiding conflicts of interest and partiality; communicating ethical requirements; confronting unacceptable conduct; and obligations to communities. International guidelines for ethical review of epidemiological studies were published by the Council of International Organizations of Medical Sciences (1991) and recently revised. The CIOMS guidelines draw a distinction between epidemiological research and routine practice (e.g., outbreak investigations and public health surveillance) and consider some of the issues associated with obtaining informed consent in epidemiological studies. Specific ethical issues arising in epidemiological research and public health practice that have been highlighted in ethical guidelines include minimizing risks and providing benefits, informed consent, avoiding and disclosing conflicts of interest, obligations to communities, and the institutional review board system.

Minimizing Risks And Providing Benefits

Ethical concerns in epidemiology and public health practice often relate to the obligations of health professionals to acquire and apply scientific knowledge aimed at maintaining and restoring public health while respecting individual rights. Potential societal benefits must often be balanced with risks and potential harms to individuals and communities, such as the potential for stigmatization or invasion of privacy.

Epidemiologists have ethical and professional obligations to maximize the potential benefits of studies to research participants and to society and to minimize potential harms and risks. In addition, these obligations are often legal or regulatory requirements such as U.S. federal regulations protecting human research participants (45 CFR 46). The risks of epidemiological studies and practice activities can be minimized by rigorously protecting the confidentiality of health information, as discussed below. Although the risks posed by epidemiological studies are often minor compared with those that may be associated with clinical trials and other experimental studies, participants in epidemiological studies may be burdened by a loss of privacy, by time spent completing interviews and examinations, and by possible adverse psychological effects such as enhanced grief or anxiety. Such risks and potential harms can be minimized by careful attention to study procedures and questionnaire design, for example, by limiting the length of interviews or by scheduling them on a date that is less likely to result in adverse psychological effects.

Minimizing risks and potential harms and maximizing potential benefits are particularly important in epidemiological studies of vulnerable populations. Examples include studies of children, prisoners, some elderly people, and populations that are marginalized or socioeconomically disadvantaged.

A further obligation is the need to ensure that the burdens and potential benefits of epidemiological studies are distributed equitably. The potential benefits of epidemiological research are often societal in nature, such as obtaining new information about the causes of diseases or identifying health disparities across groups defined by race, ethnicity, socioeconomic status, or other factors. Research participants may receive direct benefits from participation in some studies, such as when a previously unrecognized disease or risk factor is detected during examinations. The balance of risks and potential benefits of epidemiological studies are considered not only by individual researchers but also by members of human subject committees such as institutional review boards in the United States.

Avoiding And Disclosing Conflicts Of Interest

Other ethical issues that arise in the professional practice of epidemiology relate to how best to deal with potential conflicts of interest in order to maintain public trust in epidemiology and sustain public support for health research. Periodic media reports about previously undisclosed conflicts of interest in the United States and other countries have raised public awareness of the potential for conflicts of interest in clinical research and epidemiology and about the need for institutions and individual researchers to address such conflicts. Conflicts of interest can affect scientific judgment and harm scientific objectivity. Studies have suggested that financial interests and researchers’ commitment to a hypothesis can influence reported research results. To address such concerns, funding agencies and research institutions have taken steps such as adopting new training programs that encourage researchers to avoid or disclose conflicts of interest and revising or strengthening institutional rules and guidelines. Professional societies and medical associations have also issued policy statements and recommendations about how best to address conflicts of interest in clinical research. Researchers should disclose financial interests and sources of funding when publishing research results. It may also be important to disclose information about potential or actual financial conflicts of interest when obtaining informed consent from research participants. A related issue is that health researchers should avoid entering into contractual agreements that prevent them from publishing results in a timely manner. Communicating research results in a timely manner without censorship or interference from the funder is important for maintaining public trust.

Obligations To Communities

The obligations of epidemiologists to study participants are especially important to consider. These obligations include communicating the results of epidemiological studies at the earliest possible time after appropriate scientific peer review so that the widest possible audience stands to benefit from the information. Epidemiologists should strive to carry out studies in a way that is scientifically valid and interpret and report the results of their studies in a way that is scientifically accurate and appropriate. In addition, epidemiologists should respect cultural diversity in carrying out studies and in communicating with members of affected communities. Other obligations to community members and to research participants have been highlighted in ethical guidelines for epidemiologists and public health institutions.

Informed Consent

Informed consent provisions in public health studies ensure that research participants make a free choice and also give institutions the legal authorization to proceed with the research. Investigators must disclose information that potential participants use to decide whether to consent to the study. This includes the purpose of the research, the scientific procedures, anticipated risks and benefits, any inconveniences or discomfort, and the participant’s right to refuse participation or to withdraw from the research at any time [45 Code of Federal Regulations (CFR) 46]. Informed consent requirements may be waived in exceptional circumstances, when obtaining consent is impractical, the risks are minimal, and the risks and potential benefits of the research have been carefully considered by an independent review committee. For example, in some epidemiology studies involving the analysis of large databases of routinely collected information (e.g., insurance claims data), it may not be feasible to recontact patients to ask them for their informed consent. Risks and potential harms in such studies may be very low, and risks may be further reduced by omitting personal identifiers from the computer databases.

Special considerations for obtaining informed consent may arise in public health studies of socioeconomically deprived people. People who have limited access to health care may misunderstand an invitation to participate in a study as an opportunity to receive medical care. In addition, they may be reluctant to refuse participation when the researcher is viewed as someone in a position of authority such as a physician or university professor. Socioeconomically deprived people may also be more motivated to participate in studies involving financial incentives for participation. A further issue is that there is often a need to translate informed consent statements into a language other than English. The important issues that arise in international research conducted by researchers from countries such as the United States and Great Britain in developing countries have also received considerable attention (CIOMS 1991).

Privacy And Confidentiality

One important way in which public health researchers reduce potential harms and risks to participants in epidemiological studies is by rigorously protecting the confidentiality of their health information. Specific measures taken by researchers to protect the confidentiality of health information include keeping records under lock and key, limiting access to confidential records, discarding personal identifiers from data collection forms and computer files whenever feasible, and training staff in the importance of privacy and confidentiality protection. Other measures that have been employed to safeguard health information include encrypting computer databases, limiting geographic detail, and suppressing cells in tabulated data, where the number of cases in the cell is small.

In the United States, the Health Insurance Portability and Accountability Act (HIPAA) of 1996 took effect early in 2004 after extensive discussion. The new regulations provide protection for the privacy of certain individually identifiable health data referred to as protected health information. The privacy rules permit disclosures without individual authorization to public health authorities authorized by law to collect or receive the information for the purpose of preventing or controlling disease, injury, or disability, including public health practice activities such as surveillance.

The Institutional Review Board System

The purpose of research ethics committees or institutional review boards (IRBs) is to ensure that studies involving human research participants are designed to conform to relevant ethical standards and that the rights and welfare of participants are protected. Human-subject review by such committees ensures that studies have a favorable balance of potential benefits and risks, that participants are selected equitably, and that procedures for obtaining informed consent are adequate. In the United States, federal regulations to protect human research subjects (45 CFR 46) have resulted in a complex IRB system. Similar safeguards exist in many other countries.

Despite the important role played by research ethics committees and IRBs, researchers have sometimes expressed concern about the obstacles that human-subject review can create. In some countries, human-subject review has been streamlined with the use of standardized forms and review processes or by centralizing review by research ethics committees. As previously mentioned, one of the important issues considered by research ethics committees and by individual researchers is the adequacy of provisions for obtaining the informed consent of study participants.

These are just some of the ethical issues addressed in ethical guidelines developed for epidemiologists and other public health professionals. Other issues addressed in the guidelines include those pertaining to scientific misconduct, intellectual property and data sharing, publication of research findings, and cross-cultural or international health research.

Ethical Issues In Public Health Practice

An expanding body of literature has considered the important ethical issues that arise in such areas of public health practice as surveillance, emergency responses, and program evaluation (Snider and Stroup 1997; Thacker and Berkelman 1988; Wetterhall et al. 1992; Coughlin 1997). In further specifying ethical norms in particular contexts, it is important to draw distinctions between epidemiological research and public health practice activities. For example, requirements for submitting research protocols to an IRB do not necessarily apply to outbreak investigations and other emergency responses.

Definitions Of Surveillance, Emergency Responses, And Program Evaluation

Surveillance can be defined as the ongoing systematic collection, analysis, and interpretation of outcome-specific data, with the timely dissemination of these data to those responsible for preventing and controlling disease or injury. A fundamental public health activity is to measure and monitor changes in health status, risk factors, and health service access and utilization. The effective dissemination of information is as important as data collection and analysis; the collected information must have a demonstrated utility.

Emergency responses and outbreak investigations can be defined as public health activities undertaken in an urgent or emergency situation, usually because of an imminent health threat to the population. Sometimes, this is because the public or government authorities perceive an imminent threat that demands immediate action. The primary purpose of the activity is to determine the nature and magnitude of a public health problem in the community and to implement appropriate measures to address the problem (Snider and Stroup 1997).

Field epidemiology and investigations of disease outbreaks require us to consider when the data are sufficient to take action rather than to ask what additional questions might be answered by the data. The guidelines and approaches for conducting epidemiological field investigations reflect the urgency of determining the extent of an outbreak and the need to make practical recommendations such as during the 2014 outbreak of Ebola hemorrhagic fever. Program evaluation, on the other hand, refers to the systematic application of scientific and statistical procedures for measuring program conceptualization, design, implementation, and utility; the comparison of these measurements; and the use of the resulting information to optimize program outcomes.

Federal regulations (Title 45 CFR Part 46), which deal with issues such as IRB review and informed consent requirements, mostly address biomedical research. These regulations define research as a systematic investigation including development, testing, and evaluation designed to develop or contribute to generalizable knowledge. Although some public health activities can clearly be classified as either research or nonresearch activities for regulatory purposes, for other activities the classification is more difficult. For example, scientific knowledge generated in controlling a disease outbreak may turn out to be useful in other settings even though generating generalizable knowledge was not the primary intent of the investigation.

In applying the federal regulations for protecting participants in public health research, U.S. agencies have distinguished health research and nonresearch public health practice activities. Research and nonresearch activities cannot be easily defined by the methods that are employed. For example, questionnaire development, laboratory analysis, and logistic regression techniques are commonly employed in etiologic studies with a case–control design as well as in many case–control studies conducted as part of outbreak investigations. To address this issue, guidelines from the Centers for Disease Control and Prevention state that the major difference between research and nonresearch lies in the primary intent of the activity. The primary intent of research is to generate or contribute to generalizable knowledge. The primary intent of nonresearch activities in public health practice is to prevent disease or injury, improve health, and ensure the efficient and effective use of resources.

For example, surveillance projects are likely to be nonresearch when they involve the regular, ongoing collection and analysis of health-related data conducted to monitor the frequency and distribution of diseases and health conditions in the population. Surveillance projects may have a research component when they involve the collection and analysis of health-related data conducted either to generate knowledge that is applicable to other populations and settings or to contribute to general knowledge about the health condition. Most emergency responses and outbreak investigations tend to be nonresearch because these projects are undertaken to solve an immediate health problem and any knowledge gained will likely benefit only the study participants or target population.

Although some ethical requirements such as IRB review do not apply equally to epidemiological research and nonresearch public health practice activities, there are many important similarities between the ethics of epidemiological research and nonresearch (e.g., requirements for confidentiality protection in research and nonresearch disease surveillance systems). Investigators should carefully consider ethical issues in each project regardless of whether it is research or public health practice.

Ethical Issues In Public Health Surveillance

 Ethical guidelines for public health surveillance have been developed for disease registry personnel, and a growing body of literature has evolved in this area. These developments are partly a response to public concern over the privacy and confidentiality of health information and technological advances such as the use of the Internet to disseminate data from surveillance systems and disease registries.

Data collected through surveillance systems provide for the ongoing evaluation of disease risk factors, incidence, and mortality and allow for the evaluation of health care utilization, treatment, and disease prevention and control activities. These and other benefits of public health surveillance must be balanced against possible risks and harms such as infringements on personal privacy. The need to balance potential benefits against risks underlines the rule that surveillance data should not be collected if they will not be used. Thus, public health professionals have ethical obligations to both maximize the potential benefits of routinely collected surveillance and disease registry data and minimize risks and potential harms. Steps taken to assure the quality of data collected by public health surveillance systems and disease registries maximize the potential benefits of the data. Registry data must be accurate, complete, and timely.

Potential harms and risks from the collection and use of surveillance and registry data include loss of privacy and harms resulting from breaches of confidentiality. These risks are remote possibilities because of the steps taken by public health professionals to safeguard the confidentiality of personally identifiable records in surveillance systems and registries such as data encryption, written policies and procedures for confidentiality and disclosure of data, and training of staff.

The privacy rules included in HIPAA permit disclosures without individual authorization to public health authorities who can legally collect or receive the information for the purpose of preventing or controlling disease, injury, or disability. This includes public health practice activities such as surveillance.

The risks and potential harms of public health interventions include ineffective, counterproductive, or harmful interventions; unanticipated consequences; and labeling or stigmatizing of individuals. For example, concern has been raised over the stigmatization of persons returning to the United States from West African countries affected by the Ebola hemorrhagic virus epidemic. Undue stress upon the individual’s role in the cause of illness could lead to a “blame the victim” mentality. The dilemma is how to advise people that they might be at risk for potentially serious health complications without labeling them, contributing to their anxiety, or adversely affecting their well-being.

Ethical considerations for prevention trials and community interventions include an assessment of risks and benefits, the need for voluntary participation and avoidance of excessive incentives, and justice-related issues. There is a need for sensitivity to ethnic and cultural habits and norms and to avoid “top-down” planning in which the health concerns and self-defined information needs of the target population are ignored in favor of professional preoccupations and concerns. Such concerns have been successfully addressed through community-based participatory research, which is a collaborative, empowering process that helps develop competencies in communities. Ethical issues in health communication include the need to avoid conflicts of interest, to present facts about health hazards or health opportunities in a truthful, balanced, and timely fashion, and to avoid distorting the facts or concealing ambiguities in the scientific evidence.

Conclusion

The considerable interest in ethical issues in epidemiological research and public health practice reflects both the important societal role of epidemiology and public interest in the scientific integrity of health information and the equitable distribution of health care resources. Attention to ethical issues can facilitate the effective planning, implementation, and growth of a variety of public health programs and research activities. Public health ethics is consistent with the prevention orientation of public health. Ethical concerns can be identified and effectively addressed through careful analysis.

Bibliography :

  1. American College of Epidemiology. (2000). Ethics guidelines. Annals of Epidemiology, 10, 487–497.
  2. Beauchamp, T. L. (1996). Moral reasoning. In S. S. Coughlin & T. L. Beauchamp (Eds.), Ethics and epidemiology. New York: Oxford University Press.
  3. Beauchamp, T. L., Cook, R. R., & Fayerweather, W. E. (1991). Ethical guidelines for epidemiologists. Journal of Clinical Epidemiology, 44(Suppl I), 151S–169S.
  4. Childress, J. F., Faden, R. R., Gaare, R. D., Gostin, L. O., Kahn, J., Bonnie, R. J., Kass, N. E., Mastroianni, A. C., Moreno, J. D., & Nieburg, P. (2002). Public health ethics: Mapping the terrain. Journal of Law, Medcine & Ethics, 30, 170–178.
  5. Coughlin, S. S. (1997). Ethics in epidemiology and public health practice. In S. S. Coughlin (Ed.), Ethics in epidemiology and public health practice: Collected works. Columbus: Quill Publications.
  6. Coughlin, S. S., Soskolne, C. L., & Goodman, K. W. (1997). Case analysis and moral reasoning. In S. S. Coughlin, C. L. Soskolne, & K. W. Goodman (Eds.), Case studies in public health ethics. Washington, DC: American Public Health Association.
  7. Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences. (1991). International guidelines for ethical review of epidemiological studies. Law, Medicine & Health Care, 19, 247–258.
  8. Snider, D. E., & Stroup, D. F. (1997). Defining research when it comes to public health. Public Health Reports, 112, 29–112.
  9. Soskolne, C. L., & Light, A. (1996). Towards ethics guidelines for environmental epidemiologists. Science of the Total Environment, 184, 137–147.
  10. Thacker, S. B., & Berkelman, R. L. (1988). Public health surveillance in the United States. Epidemiologic Reviews, 10, 164–190.
  11. Wetterhall, S. F., Pappaioanou, M., & Thacker, S. B. (1992). The role of public health surveillance: Information for effective action in public health. Morbidity and Mortality Weekly Report, 41(Suppl), 207–218.
  12. Dawson, A. (Ed.). (2009). The philosophy of public health. Surrey: Ashgate Publishing Limited.
  13. Kass, N. E. (2004). Public health ethics: From foundations and frameworks to justice and global public health. Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 32, 232–242.
  14. Public Health Leadership Society. (2000). Principles of the ethical practice of public health. https://www.apha.org/-/media/files/pdf/membergroups/ethics/ethics_brochure.ashx
  15. Soskolne, C. L. (1989). Epidemiology: Questions of science, ethics, morality and law. American Journal of Epidemiology, 129, 1–18.

AIDS Research Paper
Obesity Research Paper

ORDER HIGH QUALITY CUSTOM PAPER


Always on-time

Plagiarism-Free

100% Confidentiality
Special offer! Get 10% off with the 24START discount code!